The moral
argument for the existence of God is one of the most useful arguments. It goes
like this:
- Without God, moral absolutes can’t exist.
- Moral absolutes do exist.
Conclusion:
Therefore, God exists!
Premise #1: Without God, moral
absolutes can’t exist.
Most agree
that we are wired for moral truths. Piaget and Kohlberg demonstrated that children’s
moral judgments develop as their brain develops. More recently, there’s been a
rash of books confirming this, and even going further to establish that even
the belief in God is determined by our nervous system.
However, many of these same people maintain that our moral wiring is merely a product of a mindless and purposeless process – evolution. Consequently, our moral sentiments are merely the product of nature and nurture, not a purposeful Law-giver. Therefore, they do not believe that our moral wiring represents objective morality (moral absolutes). Also, they point to the relative nature of morality and insist that it is merely a cultural artifact, humanly created, with some guidance from our genome.
However, many of these same people maintain that our moral wiring is merely a product of a mindless and purposeless process – evolution. Consequently, our moral sentiments are merely the product of nature and nurture, not a purposeful Law-giver. Therefore, they do not believe that our moral wiring represents objective morality (moral absolutes). Also, they point to the relative nature of morality and insist that it is merely a cultural artifact, humanly created, with some guidance from our genome.
Therefore,
they gladly acknowledge that there can be no moral absolutes without a God
laying them out.
Premise #2: Moral absolutes do exist.
This premise
is the battleground. Although morality represents a law in a similar way that
gravity represents a physical law, it is a bit more tricky to prove the
existence of objective moral law. Why? Its effects cannot be precisely measured
and calculated as can the effects of gravity. Instead, in order to prove the
existence of moral absolutes, we have to examine ourselves and other human
beings.
C.S. Lewis
famously reasoned that making objective moral judgments is unavoidable:
·
Whenever
you find a man who says he does not believe in a real Right and Wrong, you will
find the same man going back on this a moment later. He may break his promises
to you, but if you try breaking one to him he will be complaining, ‘It’s not
fair.’
·
If
we do not believe in decent behavior, why should we be so anxious to make
excuses for not having behaved decently? The truth is we believe in decency so
much—we feel the Rule of Law pressing on us so—that we cannot bear to face the
fact that we are breaking it, and consequently we try to shift the
responsibility. (Mere Christianity)
At this
point, the Darwinist readily admits that, although programmed for morality,
this programming is the product of blind, purposeless evolution:
·
Darwinist: I might react morally, but I know that this reaction is not a product
of some higher truth hanging out there somewhere, but merely of the way that
the forces of natural selection biologically equipped our race. As a result, I
don’t see this as any proof of moral absolutes or that there’s a God who is
somehow setting the rules of the game. It’s just a matter of our wiring!
However, it
seems that Paul had anticipated the atheistic challenge and offered a rebuttal:
· You, therefore, have no excuse, you
who pass judgment on someone else, for at whatever point you judge the
other, you are condemning yourself, because you who pass judgment do the same
things (Romans 2:1).
Although the
atheist claims that there is no absolute basis for judgment, he too judges as
if he believes in absolute moral standards. According to Paul, the moral
impulse is more than a programmed knee-jerk reaction. It’s also something that
we make our own! Just watch
the atheist for five minutes, and you will see that he agrees with Paul, at
least with his behavior. The atheist passes judgments as quickly as the theist.
When someone pushes him, he’ll want an apology. He doesn’t say:
·
Although
I had this moral knee-jerk reaction, I can’t really hold you accountable for
pushing me, since there are no absolute moral truths, and therefore, there no
moral rules of right and wrong which you have violated. So I have no absolute basis
to judge your behavior.
Instead, the atheist becomes indignant
and remains indignant long after the
knee-jerk reaction passes, proving that he endorses
the charge that he has absolutely and objectively been wronged. It is this
endorsement, and not merely a knee-jerk reaction, that makes him a hypocrite. On
the one hand, he passes absolute,
objective judgment, while on the other hand, he claims that there is no higher
standard than himself by which to judge! It is also this endorsement that makes
him the object of wrath:
· But because of your stubbornness and
your unrepentant heart, you are storing up wrath against yourself for the day
of God's wrath, when his righteous judgment will be revealed (Romans 2:5).
We all believe in objective moral law. While we might deny it with our
mouths, we affirm it with our behavior, which mocks our assertion that “Morality
is just something we make up.”
We also observe that this internal moral law pays dividends. When we act
in concert with its demands, we are benefitted and tend to feel at peace. Mental
health professionals recognize that living in accordance with our moral
convictions is an important factor for mental health. Accordingly, Karen Wright
wrote,
· Eudemonia
refers to a state of well-being and full functioning that derives from a sense
of living in accordance with one’s deeply held values. (“Psychology Today,” May 2008, 76)
This is so obvious. Even atheists perceive this and are intent upon
living moral lives. However, they ascribe their moral programming to evolution.
For example, Richard Dawkins writes:
· Natural
selection, in ancestral times when we lived in small stable bands like baboons,
programmed into our brains altruistic urges, alongside sexual urges, hunger
urges, xenophobic urges and so on. (“The
God Delusion,” 221)
According to Dawkins, altruism has nothing to do with truth or an
objective right and wrong, but chance processes. Why then follow the
“altruistic urges?” Appealing to our genetic programming isn’t adequate. Should
we be “xenophobic” (fearful of strangers) merely because we had been
“programmed” with this reaction? Of course not! Why then be altruistic? For the
atheist, the only possible answer is pragmatic. Altruistic behavior works; it
benefits the doer. It makes you feel good and also those around you. It’s
solely a matter of cost/benefit analysis.
Atheist, humanist, and author of Humanist Manifesto II, Paul Kurtz affirms
that pragmatism is the “only” possible justification for morality:
· How are
these principles [of equality, freedom, etc.] to be justified? They are not
derived from a divine or natural law nor do they have a special metaphysical
[beyond the material world] status. They are rules offered to govern how we
shall behave. They can be justified only by reference to their results. (“Understanding the Times,” 237)
However, this stance isn’t adequate. Sometimes it isn’t pragmatic to be
moral. Hiding Jews from the Nazis wouldn’t pass the cost/benefit analysis. The
price of a bullet in the head of the entire family is just too high! Therefore,
the non-theist cannot live in accord with their rationale and the law of God
written upon their conscience (Rom. 2:14-15). Either they hide Jews and violate
their pragmatic rationale or they don’t hide Jews and violate their conscience.
Heart and mind (pragmatism) are divided and in conflict. In either case, their
mental well-being will suffer, because they are unable to live “in accordance
with one’s deeply held values.”
More fundamentally, the one who denies God and therefore denies the moral
absolutes of the conscience will fail to derive the benefits of “eudemonia.”
There is little satisfaction in living in accordance with the dictates of the
conscience if we understand it to be no more than a tyrannical electro-chemical
reaction that demands us to make sacrifices that go against our desires and
then punishes us with guilt feelings, which might have made some sense when we
were baboons. In other words, just take a conscience-numbing drug!
While pragmatic, cost/benefit thinking
can serve to justify living by our conscience, it can also serve evil. Serial
killer, Ted Bundy, had confessed to over 30 gruesome murders. He explained his
cost/benefit rationale before his execution:
·
“Then
I learned that all moral judgments are ‘value judgments,’ that all value judgments
are subjective [it just depends on how you think about them], and that none can
be proved to be either ‘right’ or ‘wrong’…I discovered that to become truly
free, truly unfettered, I had to become truly uninhibited. And I quickly
discovered that the greatest obstacle to my freedom, the greatest block and
limitation to it, consists in the insupportable “value judgment that I was
bound to respect the rights of others. I asked myself, who were these ‘others?’
Other human beings with human rights? Why is it more wrong to kill a human
animal than any other animal, a pig or a sheep or a steer? Is your life more to
you than a hog’s life to a hog? Why should I be willing to sacrifice my
pleasure more for the one than for the other? Surely, you would not, in this
age of scientific enlightenment, declare that God or nature has marked some
pleasures as ‘moral’ or ‘good’ and others as ‘immoral’ or ‘bad’? In any case,
let me assure you, my dear young lady, that there is absolutely no comparison
between the pleasure I might take in eating ham and the pleasure I anticipate
in raping and murdering you. That is the honest conclusion to which my
education has led me – after the most conscientious examination of my
spontaneous and uninhibited self.” (“Christian Research Journal,” Vol 33, No 2,
2010, 32)
Skeptics will
argue that even if believing in and living by moral absolutes brings benefits,
the benefits do not prove the case for these absolutes. However, if the skeptic
justifies his behavior on the basis of pragmatic cost/benefit analysis, why
then is he closed to this rationale when used by theists? Sounds like a double
standard.
Besides,
moral law reflects elegance in design in the same way that the law of gravity
reflects elegance. When we wrong our wife, we feel guilty. When we apologize,
we feel relieved, knowing that we have done the right thing. When she forgives,
we feel restored and encouraged.
This elegance
reflects a design. Not only that, it is universal and also seems to have been
unchanged, as evidenced by our earliest records.
Was Bundy tormented
by his deeds? Did he eventually repent of them? We are informed that he did.
Interestingly, even our legal system has a demonstrated high regard for deathbed
confessions. Why? Because our legal elites have noted a common pattern – that we
are so convinced of the truth of this moral law written on our conscience, that
we need to make the record-right even as we face death. If instead, we merely
regarded these moral promptings as biochemical reactions, well, why even bother
with them in light of facing a more overwhelming fate – death?
Conclusion: Deep inside, we believe in an
absolute moral law, despite the teachings of Darwin. And if there is an
absolute moral law, then there must be an absolute moral law-Giver.
IS IT POSSIBLE TO HAVE OBJECTIVE MORAL
LAW WITHOUT A MORAL LAW-GIVER?
Most
atheists and agnostics believe in moral relativism: Morality is created or
invented relative to our desires, upbringing, feelings, and the dictates of our
society. And because it is created, rather than discovered (existing
objectively apart from ourselves), it changes as we and our society change.
This means that torturing babies might be “wrong” for one society but not for
another.
However,
a small number of atheists and agnostics are objective moral realists. They
believe in an unchanging objective set of moral laws, which exist apart from
ourselves and are therefore discovered rather than created. Consequently, they
believe that torturing babies is wrong no matter what time or in what culture
you might live.
As a
Christian, I also believe that there are immutable and universal objective
moral laws. Therefore, I applaud others who believe in moral laws and regard
them as real and immutable as the law of gravity. However, I must point out the
problems in believing in moral law without a moral law-Giver.
The
atheist cannot adequately account for such laws in his exclusively
materialistic worldview. While the atheist might insist that the moral laws are
merely a part of the material universe, this seems unlikely:
MATERIALS
ARE MOLECULES-IN-MOTION. Meanwhile, moral law, as are the
physical laws, is immutable.
MATERIAL
REALITY DIFFERS GREATLY FROM PLACE-TO-PLACE. The Goby Desert is greatly
different from the bottom of the Indian Ocean or Mars. Moral absolutes could
not be objective or absolute if they differed in Alaska and the Congo. So too,
the law of gravity! What then would explain the fact that moral law is universal?
Consequently, the moral laws must rest upon something that transcends this varied
material universe.
MATERIAL
REALITY CANNOT EXPLAIN OR ACCOUNT FOR OUR ELEGANT AND THEREFORE KNOWABLE LAWS
OF PHYSICS AND MORALITY. Even the chemical table exhibits
profound elegance and design. What can explain such elegance in the material
world apart from an intelligent Designer? Besides, a changing material world
cannot begin to explain the existence of unchanging laws.
There
is also elegance in the operation of the moral laws. Following the moral laws
bring harmony, order, and peace. We do wrong, and we feel guilty. We confess
our sin (and perhaps make necessary reparations), and we feel better.
Relationships are restored. Or instead, we attempt to justify ourselves and
must harden our conscience accordingly, as we obsessively wage an inner war to
prove ourselves right and, in the process, weaken relationships.
MORAL
LAW ALSO MUST BE AUTHORITATIVE. It must carry the authority to tell us that we
have done either wrongly and to require a price for wrongdoing. It communicates
through the compelling feelings of guilt and shame. Consequently, we are
coerced to make excuses and justify ourselves. However, there is nothing in the
merely physical world that can communicate our guilt with any authority, even
though God’s laws are written into our conscience:
- For when Gentiles, who do not have the law, by nature do what the law requires, they are a law to themselves, even though they do not have the law. They show that the work of the law is written on their hearts, while their conscience also bears witness, and their conflicting thoughts accuse or even excuse them on that day when, according to my gospel, God judges the secrets of men by Christ Jesus. (Romans 2:14-16; ESV)
However,
if we believe that these implanted moral laws are no more than biochemical
reactions, they carry no authority. Why not? If moral law is no more than a
biochemical reaction, then there is no overriding reason to obey it. Why not
just take a pill to quiet down our troubling conscience!
This is
because a biochemical reaction merely communicates what is, not what authoritatively ought
to be (morality). My computer might flash a screen at me reading, “You have
not treated me properly.” However, these words carry no authority. Although it
might shut itself down if I didn’t follow the proper procedures, it cannot
censure me morally. I can simply have it repaired without any damage to my
conscience. Without an Authority underpinning our feelings of guilt, our
strategy should likewise be a matter of having the conscience repaired.
Besides,
what is impersonal (the physical world) cannot be morally offended as you and I
might be. If the physical universe is the source of moral law, I cannot offend
it by yelling at it. I can curse at my computer without breaking a moral law.
However, if I scream at my wife or my subordinate, this is entirely a different
matter.
Buddhists
and Hindus also believe in a moral law – karma. However, without a law-Giver,
how can karma be justly administered? Without Intelligence, how is karmic
justice to be administered in light of the many moral nuances that must be
considered?
Besides,
we can defy physical laws like gravity, without consequence, by flying on a
plane. However, we cannot take a pill to cleanse a guilty conscience, not for
long, at least. Morality cannot be successfully side-stepped.
Moral
problems must be addressed with moral answers. However, a material world can
offer no explanation or remedy (just palliatives) for moral problems. We can
take an antibiotic to cure giardia, but there does not exist an antibiotic for
guilt.
In his
essay “Fact and Value,” Leonard Peikoff argued that there are objective moral
principles or laws embedded in the physical reality – the “is” - of this cosmos:
- As Ayn Rand states the point in “The Objectivist Ethics”: “Knowledge, for any conscious organism, is the means of survival; to a living consciousness, every ‘is‘ implies an ‘ought.’” (http://www.peikoff.com/essays_and_articles/fact-and-value/)
But how
it is that “every ‘is‘ implies an ‘ought?’” A car can place no demand on us
that it “ought” to be driven. Nor can an apple demand that it “ought” to be
eaten. Instead, it seems that the “is” and the “ought” occupy separate,
although adjacent, worlds.
Ordinarily,
they do, but Peikoff unites them by secretly introducing his own “ought” to
connect the non-moral “is” to the “ought”:
- Every fact of reality which we discover has, directly or indirectly, an implication for man’s self-preservation and thus for his proper course of action. In relation to the goal of staying alive, the fact demands specific kinds of actions and prohibits others; i.e., it entails a definite set of evaluations. For instance, sunlight is a fact of metaphysical reality; but once its effects are discovered by man and integrated to his goals, a long series of evaluations follows: the sun is a good thing.
“The
fact demands specific kinds of actions and prohibits others” only because
Peikoff’s “ought” requires the facts to do so. The facts are to serve his
“ought” – “man’s self-preservation.” Consequently, “the sun is a good thing.”
Why? Because it serves our “ought” of “self-preservation!”
But
from where did this “ought” of “self-preservation” come? Not from the facts!
The facts of existence are silent about human priority or exceptionalism. They
say nothing of a human value or importance that exceeds the value of termites,
mosquitos, bacteria, or hogs. (The concept of value requires us to question –
“Valuable to whom?” Certainly to humans, but this is just a subjective
assessment.) Instead, in order to
salvage “The Objectivist Ethics,” Peikoff was forced to inject his own
subjective value of “man’s self-preservation.” (If the hog could speak, he’d
speak of “hogs’ preservation.) However, this makes his entire moral system subjective. All of the facts are
subjectively coerced into serving his own value of “man’s self-preservation.”
Yet, I
appreciate Peikoff’s attempt at trying to formulate an objective system of
morality. However, moral law requires a moral law-Giver. There is only one
objective basis for morality, the “ought” – the One immutable, omniscient, and
universal God, who demands the very morality He has written on our conscience.
A world
without God is a world where anything goes, and the worst deeds are met with
silence. The humanist Max Hocutt had aptly written:
· “To me [the non-existence of
God] means that there is no absolute morality, that moralities are sets of
social conventions devised by humans to satisfy their needs…If there were a
morality written up in the sky somewhere but no God to enforce it, I see no
good reason why anyone should pay it any heed.” (David Noebel, Understanding the Times)
Hocutt’s statement puts the kibosh on
the idea that we can have moral absolutes without a moral law-Giver.
We must bear
in mind the distinction between objective and subjective morality (moral
relativism). Since subjective, man-made morality is merely a matter of what
seems right, there is no way that the subjectivist can bring an objective
charge against God.
Let me
illustrate. The skeptic often claims that God is a monster because He condemns
people to endless punishment. However, you can retort:
·
Well,
what’s the problem if He does condemn eternally if it is just a matter of you
personally not liking this idea? Although you claim to be a moral relativist,
you are judging God as if He violated an absolute standard. However, according
to your worldview, He merely violated your personal feelings. You can’t have it
both ways. If you are a moral relativist, you cannot pronounce objective
indictments.
No comments:
Post a Comment