Does the rejection of God also entail the rejection of any
possible basis for objective moral truth? Atheist and former president and CEO
of the Center for Inquiry, Ronald A.
Lindsay, argues that we do not need God to be good. However, he also understands
that it is almost impossible to talk about being good unless there exists an objective
good. What, then, can be the basis of this objective good once God is rejected?
Can’t the objective moral good be based upon certain facts
like “pain is a bad thing…and people avoid being in pain” or “well-being is a
good thing?” Putting aside the question of whether or not these “facts” are
correct, Lindsey admits to another problem – What is factually true doesn’t
automatically mean that we ought to do something about it. For example, the
mere fact that our neighbor is
suffering doesn’t require us to do anything about it:
·
The difficulty in deriving moral obligations
directly from discrete facts about the world was famously noted by the
eighteenth-century Scottish philosopher David Hume, who remarked that from a
statement about how things are—an “is” statement—we cannot infer a moral norm
about how things should be—an “ought” statement.
Lindsay concludes that we cannot logically jump from a fact
to a moral obligation: “An “is” statement and an “ought” statement are distinct
classes of statements.” Consequently, there is no moral connection between what
“is” to what “ought to be,” as there is no moral connection between spilled
milk and an obligation to clean it up. Something – an absolute moral directive –
is clearly missing from this equation.
After surveying possible foundations for objective moral
truth, Lindsay admits:
·
So secular attempts to provide an objective
foundation for morality have been … well, less than successful. Does this imply
we are logically required to embrace nihilism [the belief that there is no
objective moral truth, but just personal inclinations]?
What then is Lindsay’s solution for overcoming nihilism? It
seems like more of the same. He claims that “morality is neither objective nor
subjective.” Well, what is it? It is “intersubjective,” based upon another “fact”
of our common human condition:
·
We have vulnerabilities and needs similar to
those of people who lived in ancient times and medieval times, and to those of
people who live today in other parts of the world. The obligation to tell the
truth will persist as long as humans need to rely on communications from each
other. The obligation to assist those who are in need of food and water will
persist as long as humans need hydration and nutrition to sustain themselves.
The obligation not to maim someone will persist as long as humans cannot
spontaneously heal wounds and regrow body parts. The obligation not to kill
someone will persist as long as we lack the power of reanimation. In its
essentials, the human condition has not changed much, and it is the
circumstances under which we live that influence the content of our norms, not
divine commands. Morality is a human institution serving human needs, and the
norms of the common morality will persist as long as there are humans around.”
Admittedly, what Lindsay has articulated represents our “norms
of the common morality.” However, his solution again wrongly assumes that there is a moral bridge
between the facts of our human condition and a moral requirement that we take action
to pursue the welfare of the human race.
Meanwhile, other atheists have utterly abandoned the attempt
to provide an objective basis for morality. Atheist, humanist, and author of Humanist Manifesto II, Paul Kurtz
affirms that pragmatism is the “only” possible justification for morality:
·
How are these principles [of equality, freedom,
etc.] to be justified? They are not derived from a divine or natural law nor do
they have a special metaphysical [beyond the material world] status. They are
rules offered to govern how we shall behave. They can be justified only by
reference to their results. (“Understanding
the Times,” 237)
While pragmatic, cost/benefit thinking can serve to justify
living morally, pragmatism can just as easily serve evil. Serial killer, Ted
Bundy, had confessed to over 30 gruesome murders. He explained his cost/benefit
rationale before his execution:
·
“Then I learned that all moral judgments are
‘value judgments,’ that all value judgments are subjective [it just depends on
how you think about them], and that none can be proved to be either ‘right’ or
‘wrong’…I discovered that to become truly free, truly unfettered, I had to
become truly uninhibited. And I quickly discovered that the greatest obstacle
to my freedom, the greatest block and limitation to it, consists in the
insupportable “value judgment that I was bound to respect the rights of others.
I asked myself, who were these ‘others?’ Other human beings with human rights?
Why is it more wrong to kill a human animal than any other animal, a pig or a
sheep or a steer? Is your life more to you than a hog’s life to a hog? Why
should I be willing to sacrifice my pleasure more for the one than for the
other? Surely, you would not, in this age of scientific enlightenment, declare
that God or nature has marked some pleasures as ‘moral’ or ‘good’ and others as
‘immoral’ or ‘bad’? In any case, let me assure you, my dear young lady, that
there is absolutely no comparison between the pleasure I might take in eating
ham and the pleasure I anticipate in raping and murdering you. That is the
honest conclusion to which my education has led me – after the most
conscientious examination of my spontaneous and uninhibited self.” (“Christian Research Journal,” Vol 33, No
2, 2010, 32)
Bundy demonstrated that pragmatism means different things to
different people. In fact, it can be argued that pragmatism’s cost/benefit analysis
is the lens through which we can best understand human history, not only its
high points but also its low ones. Consequently, pragmatism cannot serve as a
replacement for objective moral truths.
Besides, if an atheist truly wants to live pragmatically, he
will try out living as a Christian. Even atheists admit that such a life offers
many pragmatic benefits. Occasionally, they will even confess, “I wish that I
could have your faith.” However, in this case, they claim that the truth has to
take precedence over any benefits.
For example, Lindsay claims that, even if God does exist, he cannot rationally be the basis for objective moral truth:
For example, Lindsay claims that, even if God does exist, he cannot rationally be the basis for objective moral truth:
·
…we cannot possibly rely on God to tell us
what’s morally right and wrong. As Plato pointed out long ago in his dialogue
Euthyphro, divine commands cannot provide a foundation for morality…Rules of
conduct based on the arbitrary fiats of someone more powerful than us are not
equivalent to moral norms. Moreover, it is no solution to say that God commands
only what is good. This response presupposes that we can tell good from bad,
right from wrong, or, in other words, that we have our own independent
standards for moral goodness. But if we have such independent standards, then
we don’t need God to tell us what to do. We can determine what is morally right
or wrong on our own. https://www.secularhumanism.org/index.php/articles/5640
In Plato's dialogue Euthyphro,
Socrates asks Euthyphro, "Is the good loved by the gods because it is
good, or is it good because it is loved by the gods?" In the first
instance, God becomes irrelevant because the good exists apart from God. In the
second instance, God’s love for the good is arbitrary, and, therefore, it is
not worthy of our moral consideration.
Let me try to restate this: If God DISCOVERS morality, then God is less than God and is unnecessary; if God CREATES morality and then imposes it upon us, He is an arbitrary despot.
Let me try to restate this: If God DISCOVERS morality, then God is less than God and is unnecessary; if God CREATES morality and then imposes it upon us, He is an arbitrary despot.
What then is the solution? A third option: Morality is not
arbitrary or independent of God, because it finds its origin within the Being
of God. Besides, it is difficult to argue against God as the Source of
objective moral law in favor of our own moral conscience or reason. This is
because He has wired us with His own moral truths. Therefore, our conscience
and reason is a replica of His. Consequently, when we deny God, we also deny
our very nature, conscience and reason, created in His likeness. Therefore,
when we follow our God-given moral impulses, we are living in harmony and peace
with these implanted truths.
While many concede that objective moral absolutes cannot
exist without God, they will deny that moral absolutes, like principles of
justice, even exist. This brings us back into the clutches of nihilism.
No comments:
Post a Comment