Friday, December 15, 2017

MORAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD





The moral argument for the existence of God is one of the most useful arguments. It goes like this:

  1. Without God, moral absolutes can’t exist.
  2. Moral absolutes do exist.
 Conclusion: Therefore, God exists!

Premise #1: Without God, moral absolutes can’t exist.

Most agree that we are wired for moral truths. Piaget and Kohlberg demonstrated that children’s moral judgments develop as their brain develops. More recently, there’s been a rash of books confirming this, and even going further to establish that even the belief in God is determined by our nervous system.

However, many of these same people maintain that our moral wiring is merely a product of a mindless and purposeless process – evolution. Consequently, our moral sentiments are merely the product of nature (and nurture), not a purposeful Law-giver. Therefore, they do not believe that our moral wiring represents objective morality (moral absolutes). Why not? Moral absolutes would have to be universal and immutable. If they were merely the product of evolution, they could be neither. Instead, they would depend upon whether a group of humans possessed the latest random mutation.

Besides, even if we all shared the same genome, an “is” (our DNA) does not demand an “ought” (a moral imperative). As the late Scottish philosopher, David Hume, claimed, there is an impassable chasm between the two. Consequently, to bridge this chasm requires humanly created and arbitrary/pragmatic decisions to elevate our genetically conditioned moral feelings into evolving laws and social standards.

In his essay “Fact and Value,” Leonard Peikoff argued that there are objective moral principles or laws embedded in the physical reality – the “is” -  of this cosmos:

  • As Ayn Rand states the point in “The Objectivist Ethics”: “Knowledge, for any conscious organism, is the means of survival; to a living consciousness, every ‘is‘ implies an ‘ought.’” (http://www.peikoff.com/essays_and_articles/fact-and-value/)

But how it is that “every ‘is‘ implies an ‘ought?’” A car can place no demand on us that it “ought” to be driven. Nor can an apple demand that it “ought” to be eaten. Instead, it seems that the “is” and the “ought” occupy separate, although adjacent, worlds.

Ordinarily, they do, but Peikoff unites them by secretly introducing his own “ought” to connect the non-moral “is” to the “ought”:

  • Every fact of reality which we discover has, directly or indirectly, an implication for man’s self-preservation and thus for his proper course of action. In relation to the goal of staying alive, the fact demands specific kinds of actions and prohibits others; i.e., it entails a definite set of evaluations. For instance, sunlight is a fact of metaphysical reality; but once its effects are discovered by man and integrated to his goals, a long series of evaluations follows: the sun is a good thing.

“The fact demands specific kinds of actions and prohibits others” only because Peikoff’s “ought” requires the facts to do so. The facts are to serve his “ought” – “man’s self-preservation.” Consequently, “the sun is a good thing.” Why? Because it serves our “ought” of “self-preservation!”

But from where did this “ought” of “self-preservation” come? Not from the facts! The facts of existence are silent about human priority or exceptionalism. They say nothing of a human value or importance that exceeds the value of termites, mosquitos, bacteria, or hogs. (The concept of value requires us to question – “Valuable to whom?” Certainly to humans, but this is just a subjective assessment.)  Instead, in order to salvage “The Objectivist Ethics,” Peikoff was forced to inject his own subjective value of “man’s self-preservation.” (If the hog could speak, he’d speak of “hogs’ preservation.) However, this makes his entire moral system subjective. All of the facts are subjectively coerced into serving his own value of “man’s self-preservation.”

Yet, I appreciate Peikoff’s attempt at trying to formulate an objective system of morality. However, moral law requires a moral law-Giver. There is only one objective basis for morality, the “ought” – the One immutable, omniscient, and universal God, who demands the very morality He has written on our conscience.

However, a small number of atheists and agnostics are objective moral realists. They believe in an unchanging objective set of moral laws, which exist apart from ourselves and are therefore discovered rather than created. Consequently, they believe that torturing babies is wrong no matter what time or in what culture you might live.

As a Christian, I also believe that there are immutable and universal objective moral laws. Therefore, I applaud others who believe in moral laws and regard them as real and immutable as the law of gravity. However, I must point out the problems in believing in moral law without a moral law-Giver.

The materialist/atheist cannot adequately account for such laws in his exclusively materialistic worldview. While the atheist might insist that the moral laws are merely a part of the material universe, this seems unlikely:

Materials are molecules-in-motion. Meanwhile, objective moral law, as are the physical laws, is immutable.

Material reality differs greatly from place-to-place. Therefore it cannot be the basis for immutable and universal laws. The Gobi Desert is greatly different from the bottom of the Indian Ocean or Mars. Moral absolutes could not be objective or absolute if they differed in Alaska and the Congo. Consequently, the moral laws must rest upon something that transcends this varied material universe.

Material reality cannot explain or account for our elegant and therefore knowable laws of physics and morality. Even the chemical table exhibits profound elegance and design. What can explain such elegance in the material world apart from an intelligent Designer? Besides, a changing material world cannot begin to explain the existence of unchanging laws.

There is also elegance in the operation of the moral laws. Living in accordance with the moral laws brings harmony, order, and peace. We do wrong, and we feel guilty. We confess our sin (and perhaps make necessary reparations), and we feel better. Relationships are restored. Or instead, we attempt to justify ourselves and must harden our conscience accordingly, as we obsessively wage an inner war to prove ourselves right and, in the process, weaken relationships.

Moral law also must be authoritative. It must carry the authority to tell us that we have done either wrongly and to require a price for wrongdoing. It communicates through the compelling feelings of guilt, shame, and dissonance. Consequently, we are coerced to make excuses and justify ourselves.

Instead, if we believe that these implanted moral laws are no more than biochemical reactions, they carry no ultimate authority. Why not? If moral law is no more than a biochemical reaction, then there is no overriding reason to obey it. Why not just take a pill to quiet down our troubling conscience! 

This is because a biochemical reaction merely communicates what is, not what authoritatively ought to be (morality). My computer might flash a screen at me reading, “You have not treated me properly.” However, these words carry no authority. Although it might shut itself down if I didn’t follow the proper procedures, it cannot censure me morally. I can simply have it repaired without any damage to my conscience. Without an Authority underpinning our feelings of guilt, our strategy should likewise be a matter of having the conscience repaired.

Besides, what is impersonal (the physical world) cannot be morally offended as you and I might be. If the physical universe is the source of moral law, I cannot offend it by yelling at it. I can curse at my computer without breaking a moral law. However, if I scream at my wife or my subordinate, this is entirely a different matter.

Buddhists and Hindus also believe in a moral law (darma) which has the power to “punish” (karma). However, without a law-Giver, how can karma be justly administered? Without Intelligence, how is karmic justice to be administered in light of the many moral nuances that must be considered?

Besides, we can defy physical laws like gravity, without consequence, by flying on a plane. However, we cannot take a pill to cleanse a guilty conscience, not for long, at least. Morality cannot be successfully side-stepped.

Moral problems must be addressed with moral answers. However, a material world can offer no explanation or remedy (just palliatives) for moral problems. We can take an antibiotic to cure giardia, but there does not exist an antibiotic for guilt.

Therefore, most Western intellectuals gladly acknowledge that there can be no moral absolutes without a God laying them out. For example, Atheist Arthur Leff, Duke School of Law, wrote:

·       “The so-called death of God wasn’t just His funeral, but was the elimination of any coherent ethical or legal system…As it stands now, everything is up for grabs…Napalming babies is bad, starving the poor wicked, buying and selling people is depraved—but, ‘Sez who?’ God help us.”


Premise #2: Moral absolutes do exist.

This premise is the battleground. Although morality represents a law in a similar way that gravity represents a physical law, it is a bit more tricky to prove the existence of objective moral law. Why? Its effects cannot be precisely measured and calculated as can the effects of gravity. Instead, in order to prove the existence of moral absolutes, we have to examine ourselves and human behavior.

C.S. Lewis famously reasoned that making objective moral judgments is unavoidable:

·       Whenever you find a man who says he does not believe in a real Right and Wrong, you will find the same man going back on this a moment later. He may break his promises to you, but if you try breaking one to him he will be complaining, “It’s not fair.”

He might claim that it is just his DNA reacting. However, his thinking and behavior betray something different:

·       If we do not believe in decent behavior, why should we be so anxious to make excuses for not having behaved decently? The truth is we believe in decency so much—we feel the Rule of Law pressing on us so—that we cannot bear to face the fact that we are breaking it, and consequently we try to shift the responsibility. (Mere Christianity)

At this point, the Darwinist might protest:

·       I might react morally, but I know that this reaction is not a product of some higher truth hanging out there somewhere, but merely of the way that the forces of natural selection biologically equipped our race. It’s no more than a knee-jerk. As a result, I don’t see this as any proof of moral absolutes or that there’s a God who is somehow setting the rules of the game. It’s just a matter of our wiring!

On the contrary, it is far more than a mere knee-jerk reaction. Although the atheist claims that there is no absolute basis for judgment, he too judges as if he believes in absolute moral standards. Just watch the atheist for five minutes, and you will see that he agrees that his moral response is more than just a knee-jerk reaction. The atheist passes judgments as quickly as the theist. When someone pushes him, he’ll want an apology. He doesn’t say:

·       Although I had this moral knee-jerk reaction, I can’t really hold you accountable for pushing me, since there are no absolute moral truths, and therefore, there no moral rules of right and wrong which you have violated. So I have no absolute basis to judge your behavior.

Instead, the atheist becomes indignant and remains indignant long after the knee-jerk reaction has passed, proving that he endorses the charge that he has absolutely and objectively been wronged. It is this endorsement, and not merely a knee-jerk reaction, that demonstrates that he too believes in an absolute moral law.

We all believe in objective moral law. While we might deny it with our mouths, we affirm it with our behavior, which mocks our assertion that “Morality is just something we make up.”



Does life have an intrinsic, God-given meaning and purpose? Atheists, naturalists, materialists, and evolutionists answer “No.” Instead, we live in a mindless and meaningless universe. Therefore, we have to create our meaning and morality for ourselves.

This was the subject of a secular discussion group I just attended. One atheist stated:

  • I don’t need a god to give me meaning. I find meaning when I see a mother with her baby and the love they share.
Perhaps he does see meaning, but I also thought that there was something he failed to recognize. Therefore, I responded:

  • I think that you too acknowledge that life has a meaning apart from what we create for ourselves. Do too don’t simply ascribe your compassion to meaningless bio-chemical internal reactions. Instead, just as a Christian would, you ascribe meaning to what your bio-chemically, materially induced feelings tell you. You see in them pointing to something that transcends these reactions, which enlivens them with meaning.
Sadly, he ignored the implications of my statement, claiming that I didn’t understand him. However, I did understand.

His response was reflective of atheists and evolutionists in general. They are unable to live consistently with the materialistic implications of their beliefs that nothing has any inherent meaning or objectively moral significance. They are coerced to see meaning in places where they deny meaning. They know that there are objective moral laws and a higher meaning that define us, even as they deny these truths.


Could blind naturalistic processes account for the moral law imprinted upon our conscience? Can they account for the laws of science? Not if the natural processes had not been pre-existent and invested with God-like qualities!

We also observe that our internal moral law pays dividends. When we act in concert with its demands, we are benefited and tend to feel at peace. When we humble ourselves to apologize, we feel relief even if the other party refuses our apology. We observe that the inner struggle to try to rationalize our bad behavior diminishes.

Mental health professionals recognize that living in accordance with our moral convictions is an important factor for mental health. Accordingly, Karen Wright wrote,

·       Eudemonia refers to a state of well-being and full functioning that derives from a sense of living in accordance with one’s deeply held values. (“Psychology Today,” May 2008, 76)

This is so obvious. Even skeptics perceive this and are intent upon living moral lives, even if they ascribe their moral programming to evolution. For example, Richard Dawkins writes:

·       Natural selection, in ancestral times when we lived in small stable bands like baboons, programmed into our brains altruistic urges, alongside sexual urges, hunger urges, xenophobic urges and so on. (“The God Delusion,” 221)

According to Dawkins, altruism has nothing to do with an Intelligent Designer but chance processes. Why then follow the “altruistic urges?” Appealing to our genetic programming isn’t an adequate explanation. Should we be “xenophobic” (fearful of strangers) merely because we had been “programmed” with this reaction? Of course not! Why be altruistic? For the atheist, the only possible answer is pragmatic. Altruistic behavior works; it benefits the doer and also the recipients of altruism. It’s solely a matter of cost/benefit analysis.

Atheist, humanist, and author of Humanist Manifesto II, Paul Kurtz affirms that pragmatism is the “only” possible justification for morality:

·       How are these principles [of equality, freedom, etc.] to be justified? They are not derived from a divine or natural law nor do they have a special metaphysical [beyond the material world] status. They are rules offered to govern how we shall behave. They can be justified only by reference to their results. (“Understanding the Times,” 237)

However, this stance isn’t adequate. Sometimes it isn’t pragmatic to be moral. Hiding Jews from the Nazis wouldn’t pass the cost/benefit analysis. The price of a bullet in the head of the entire family is just too high! Therefore, the non-theist cannot live in accord with their rationale and the law of God written upon their conscience (Rom. 2:14-15). Either they hide Jews and violate their pragmatic rationale or they don’t hide Jews and violate their conscience. Heart and mind (pragmatism) are divided and in conflict. In either case, their mental well-being will suffer, because they are unable to live “in accordance with one’s deeply held values.”

More fundamentally, the one who denies God and therefore denies the moral absolutes of the conscience will fail to derive the benefits of “eudemonia.” There is little satisfaction in living in accordance with the dictates of the conscience if we understand it to be no more than a tyrannical electro-chemical reaction that demands us to make sacrifices that go against our desires and then punishes us with guilt feelings, which might have made some sense when we were baboons. In other words, just take a conscience-numbing drug!

Ultimately, pragmatic considerations cannot sustain virtue. While pragmatic, cost/benefit thinking can serve to justify living by our conscience, it can also serve evil. Serial killer, Ted Bundy, had confessed to over 30 gruesome murders. He explained his cost/benefit rationale before his execution:

·       “Then I learned that all moral judgments are ‘value judgments,’ that all value judgments are subjective [it just depends on how you think about them], and that none can be proved to be either ‘right’ or ‘wrong’…I discovered that to become truly free, truly unfettered, I had to become truly uninhibited. And I quickly discovered that the greatest obstacle to my freedom, the greatest block and limitation to it, consists in the insupportable “value judgment that I was bound to respect the rights of others. I asked myself, who were these ‘others?’ Other human beings with human rights? Why is it more wrong to kill a human animal than any other animal, a pig or a sheep or a steer? Is your life more to you than a hog’s life to a hog? Why should I be willing to sacrifice my pleasure more for the one than for the other? Surely, you would not, in this age of scientific enlightenment, declare that God or nature has marked some pleasures as ‘moral’ or ‘good’ and others as ‘immoral’ or ‘bad’? In any case, let me assure you, my dear young lady, that there is absolutely no comparison between the pleasure I might take in eating ham and the pleasure I anticipate in raping and murdering you. That is the honest conclusion to which my education has led me – after the most conscientious examination of my spontaneous and uninhibited self.” (“Christian Research Journal,” Vol 33, No 2, 2010, 32)

Skeptics will argue that even if believing in and living by moral absolutes brings benefits, the benefits do not prove the case for these absolutes. However, if the skeptic justifies his behavior and worldview on the basis of pragmatic cost/benefit analysis, why then is he closed to Christianity which brings better results? Instead, basing morality on pragmatism – the benefits – has many problems:

·       Rape and terrorism are not absolutely wrong. Consequently, pragmatism has no argument against the Bundys and the Hitlers who also invoke pragmatism for their justification.

·       It cannot provide an adequate justification for honesty or character to our children or students in light of the fact that sometimes pragmatism rules in favor of deception.

·       It cannot provide an adequate justification for law and justice, since justice is just a matter of the benefits it confers.

·       Nor can it provide a just justification for punishment.

·       It will breed cynicism. After long, few will be able to take seriously a pragmatic system when they do not see the benefits for themselves.

·       If our behaviors are to be based upon the benefits we receive, we can easily forego moral considerations, especially when they interfere with what we want.

·       I don’t think society can long thrive without the belief in moral absolutes.

Admittedly, this does not to prove the existence of moral absolutes. However, it does point out that if we are truly pragmatic, we will adopt both moral absolutes and a belief in God.

Besides, moral absolutes reflect an elegance in design in the same way that the law of gravity reflects an elegance. When we wrong our wife, we feel guilty. When we apologize, we feel relieved, knowing that we have done the right thing. When she forgives, we feel restored and encouraged.

Was Bundy tormented by his deeds? Did he eventually repent of them? We are informed that he did. Interestingly, even our legal system has a demonstrated high regard for deathbed confessions. Why? Because our legal elites have noted a common irresistible pattern – that we are so convinced of the truth of this moral law written on our conscience that we experience an overwhelming need to set the record straight as we face death. If instead we merely regarded these moral promptings as biochemical reactions, well, why even bother with them in light of facing a more overwhelming fate – death?

Conclusion: Deep inside, we believe in an absolute moral law, despite the teachings of Darwin. And if there is an absolute moral law, then there must be an absolute moral law-Giver.


Implications: A world without God is ultimately a world where anything goes, and the worst deeds are met with silence. The humanist Max Hocutt had aptly written:

·       “To me [the non-existence of God] means that there is no absolute morality, that moralities are sets of social conventions devised by humans to satisfy their needs…If there were a morality written up in the sky somewhere but no God to enforce it, I see no good reason why anyone should pay it any heed.” (David Noebel, Understanding the Times)

Hocutt’s observation puts the kibosh on the idea that we can have moral absolutes without a moral law-Giver.

We must bear in mind the distinction between objective and subjective morality (moral relativism). Since subjective, man-made morality is merely a matter of what seems right, there is no way that the subjectivist can bring an objective charge against God.

Let me illustrate. The skeptic often claims that God is a monster because He condemns people to eternal punishment. However, you can retort:

·       Well, what’s the problem if He does condemn eternally if it is just a matter of you personally not liking this idea? Although you claim to be a moral relativist, you are judging God as if He violated an absolute standard. However, according to your worldview, He merely violated your personal feelings. You can’t have it both ways. If you are a moral relativist, you cannot pronounce objective indictments.

No comments: